Informativeness and Persuasiveness

5 minute read

Why Accept the Premise?

In the previous essay in this series, we defined the ideas of necessity and sufficiency from the perspective of a Bayesian rational agent. If an argument is necessary, then if the subject were to reject the premise, they would decrease their acceptance of the conclusion. And if an argument is sufficient, then if the subject were to accept the premise, they would increase their acceptance of the conclusion.

But why would the subject accept the premise? A Bayesian rational agent only changes their beliefs in light of evidence. But what evidence has the arguer given? When someone makes an argument, all they do is assert that the premise is true. The only direct evidence is the observation that the arguer asserted that the premise was true.

For example, suppose Bob asserts that (𝐵) the sky is cloudy, in an attempt to convince Alice that (𝐴) it is going to rain today. Alice’s posterior belief in 𝐵, after hearing Bob’s argument, will be

P(B|Bob claimed that B)

If Alice can see the sky through her window and already knows the sky is cloudy, then Bob’s claim provides no new information. But if she can’t see the sky, why does the event that bob claimed that the sky was cloudy change her beliefs?

Imperfect Bayesians

There are various reasons that someone else merely asserting a premise would cause a rational human being to change their beliefs.

First, they may simply believe the person making the argument, because they find them at least somewhat trustworthy and find the premise a priori credible.

Second, even if they initially doubt the premise, they may be prompted to seek information about the claim. Bob’s assertion may prompt Alice to look out the window. Or the claim my include a link or reference to a trusted source.

Third, an argument may simply remind them of knowledge they had temporarily forgotten. My spouse reminding me I bought milk yesterday can convince me not to go to the grocery store even if it is something I already knew.

Forth, they may be convinced by reasoning that provides no new information. My belief about the answer to a math problem can change when someone shows me how to solve it. But the solution is only the logical consequence of my existing beliefs, not new information about the world.

A rational agent that actively seeks and forgets information is not exactly a perfect Bayesian. But regardless of the actual reason that the assertion causes the subject to change their beliefs, we can treat the assertion as if it were simply new information. If we assume that the assertion only directly effects the subject’s belief in 𝐵, then we can then find the prior probability distribution that would lead to the same posterior belief in 𝐵. We can then model our subject as a perfect Bayesian with beliefs represented by this probability distribution.

So we can model an imperfect Bayesian as an equivalent perfect Bayesian.

Definition of Post-Argument Belief

We’ll use the I to indicate the argument event. This is the event, which is directly observed by the subject, that agent 𝑋 argued premise 𝐵 in support of conclusion 𝐴. We always assume that the subject trusts the medium of communication, and their own senses, and so accepts 𝐼 as 100% true, even if they don’t accept 𝐵.

We use Pi to denote the Post-Argument opinion of the subject, defined as:

Pi()=P(|I)=P(|X argued B in support of A)

So for example Pi(B) is the subject’s opinion on 𝐵 after the argument event 𝐼, and Pi(A) is their opinion on 𝐴 after the argument event.

Definition of Informative

An argument that causes the subject to change their belief in the premise of the argument is informative. That is, an argument with premise 𝐵 is informative if:

Pi(B)>P(B)

An argument is said to be informative if the assertion of its premise is informative.

The difference between the prior and posterior (post-argument) belief in 𝐵 can be quantified in various ways (percent difference, absolute difference, ratio, etc.). We will focus on the absolute difference.

Definition of Informativeness

The informativeness of an argument with premise 𝐵 is:

Pi(B)P(B)

Definition of Persuasive

An argument is persuasive iff:

Pi(A)P(A)

Persuasiveness can be measured as the difference between Pi(A) and P(A), expressed as a ratio, percent difference, information gain, etc. We will focus on the absolute difference.

Definition of Persuasiveness

The persuasiveness of an argument with premise 𝐵 and conclusion 𝐴 is:

Pi(A)P(A)

Persuasiveness = Relevance × Informativeness

In Relevance and Corelevance, we introduced Jeffrey’s Rule of Conditioning, which says that if a Bayesian reasoner acquires information that has no effect other than to cause them to increase their belief in the premise, then their posterior belief in the conclusion changes according to the formula:

(1)P(A)=P(A|B¯)+P(B)R(A,B)

So if the argument is informative, their posterior belief in B will be Pi(B) and therefore their posterior belief in A will be:

Pi(A)=P(A|B¯)+Pi(B)R(A,B)

So as long as R(A,B) is not equal to zero, then a change in Pi(B) will result in a change in Pi(A). So a relevant and informative argument must also be persuasive.

In fact, persuasiveness is the product of relevance and informativeness (proof).

Pi(A)P(A)=(Pi(B)P(B))R(A,B)

Conclusion

So we can look at argument as the exchange of information among Bayesian reasoners, except the information is merely the fact that one of them asserted some premise. But these assertions can influence belief under certain conditions.

First, the assertion must be informative. The assertion itself must effectively be new information that causes the subject to change their belief in the premise (even if the assertion induces them to change their belief by actively seeking new information, fixing their reasoning, etc.).

Second, the premise must be relevant to the conclusion, which means the belief in the conclusion has a linear relationship with belief in the premise, as illustrated in Chart 1. When this is the case, the agent will necessarily revise their beliefs in the conclusion according to Jeffrey’s Rule (1). The argument can then said to be persuasive.

However, if the argument was not informative, it is not necessarily a bad argument. The subject may already believe in the premise, and it may still be a necessary argument, because the premise forms the basis for the subject’s belief in the conclusion in that the subject would change their belief in the conclusion if they were for any reason to reject the premise.

Proofs

Proof 1

Persuasiveness = Relevance × Informativeness

Pi(A)P(A)=R(A,B)(Pi(B)P(B))

Proof:

This proof uses the following equality defined in the previous essay.

(2)P(A)=P(A|B¯)+P(B)R(A,B)

Then

Pi(A)=P(A|B¯)+Pi(B)R(A,B)  (1)=P(A|B¯)+Pi(B)R(A,B)P(B)R(A,B)+P(B)R(A,B)=P(A|B¯)+(Pi(B)P(B))R(A,B)+P(B)R(A,B)=(P(A|B¯)+P(B)R(A,B))+(Pi(B)P(B))R(A,B)  (2)=P(A)+(Pi(B)P(B))R(A,B)

So:

Pi(A)P(A)=R(A,B)(Pi(B)P(B))

Updated: